*

MORE ON LIGHT

Arthur M. Young

Pre-scientific concepts of light

I would like in this chapter to go back to some opinions on light that were held long before the emergence of modern science. This is to the period around A.D. 350, when philosophers were endeavoring to rationalize the account of creation in Genesis, and before the dogma of the church had set in and discouraged speculation.

 

According to I. P. Sheldon Williams, St. Basil of Caesarea, writing in about A.D. 370, distinguished between the intelligible and the sensible world. (1) The intelligible world was outside time. The sensible world shared with it "an intelligible matter which Basil identifies with the light which illuminates the material world and is therefore the common ground of the whole universe intelligible and sensible."

It follows [says St. Basil] that light is of a more general nature than time, for time is found only in the sensible world. . . . Because light is not limited to time it was universally distributed at the moment of its creation, as it fills the whole room in which a lamp is kindled. Between the intelligible and the sensible worlds the firmament acts as a barrier, of which the solidity implied by its name is such that light may pass through it (but in a diluted form), but time cannot break out into the world above.

Now this is a most remarkable statement because it recognizes that time does not exist in the world of light, a fact known to science only since the advent of relativity!

The recognition of a basic division between an "intelligible" and a "sensible" world is common to all prescientific thought, and the belief in an intelligible world began its decline only when comprehensive theories, like that of universal gravitation, apparently made it possible to explain the phenomenal world in mechanical, or more correctly, reductive, terms. While Newton believed that the regularities of planetary motion were evidence for the divine, Laplace, his successor, did not. In answer to Napoleon, who had commented that Laplace had written his Celestial Mechanics with no reference to its Maker, Laplace replied: "Sire, I have no need of that hypothesis."

This has been the trend in the philosophy of science ever since. But a careful examination of the findings of science, as distinct from its philosophy, will disclose that at the true frontier of science this trend has reversed: as we pointed out in the preceding chapter, the more deeply the physicist prods into the foundations, the less certainty he finds. It is scientism and not science that still clings to the old determinism. It is the behaviorist, the sociologist, who "any day now" will discover the "laws" of human behavior. The layman too has endorsed the credo of determinism, perhaps because he feels that it is scientific, but also because it gives him security, it exorcises the demons of change.

 

The physicist, who was originally responsible for the doctrine (which Blake called "Newton's sleep"), has been awakened by his own experiments to the recognition that determinism as a doctrine is untenable. First alerted by Heisenberg's teaching that the fundamental particle cannot be observed without disturbing it, he has found uncertainty the rule rather than the exception, and he knows that he can predict only in the statistical sense; he cannot predict for individuals.

 

What is remarkable is that this fundamental turnabout has not been more widely disseminated. Eddington discussed the change from determinism in his delightful fable of "Canticles." The story goes that a scholar mistakes "Canticles" for a person, about whom he writes papers and to whom he attributes various works. After some years the scholar discovers that the word means "songs," and tries to correct the mistake he has made, only to find that other scholars have adopted his brain child and resent his effort to do away with their idol. They attack him with the criticism that he has no proof that "Canticles," the person, did not exist.

In the same way, determinism, invented on the basis of a misunderstanding, and now known to be false in principle, has been made policy, and its adherents challenge others to disprove it. Robert Oppenheimer observed in 1956:

. . . the worst of all possible misunderstandings would occur if psychology should be influenced to model itself after a physics which is not there any more, which has been quite outdated. (2)

Nonetheless, this has happened, and the pundits with the false dogma are making the most noise.

We should not underrate the difficulty involved. The determinism of the 19th century made a deep impact on our thinking, not because it was materialistic, but because it gave sanction to the rational mind to take over the functions which should be performed by other faculties. I am saying that it is the rationality of determinism that makes it dangerous, usurping not only the intuition of the higher mind, but practical common sense.

This is an old saying (practically a major thesis) in Zen philosophy: "The mind is the slayer of the reaI." There are other "enemies" that man has to conquer, such as his physical appetites, but the lusts of the flesh are less important today than the lusts of the mind, seducing leaders and the public alike with brain trusts, expertise, computers, the information explosion, and other forms of reliance on rational process.

The pertinence of this recital of what may be self-evident is that in the discovery of the true nature of light we have a reference, a guide which can help us set cosmology to rights with first things first. And now I am going to have to say something that may seem heretical to scientists and theologians alike.

This is that quantum physics, when understood, can provide the compass that in former times required revealed religion: it can tell us of first cause.

Let me go back to St. Basil. Here we have a Greek philosopher who makes far more profound and correct statements than did the philosophers who lived at the height of Greek civilization (4th and 5th centuries B.C.). Compare St. Basil with Aristotle. Impressive as was Aristotle's encyclopedic mind, he said nothing that would anticipate the revolutionary discoveries of modern science that were to reverse reason. Aristotle did not say that time does not exist in the world of light, nor could reason reach such a strange idea. How did St. Basil reach it? By reasoning about revealed scripture. This brings out the function of revealed religion: it supplies what reason per se cannot. We could not reason that light was the first thing to come into existence. Reason begins at the other end, with objects, and proceeds to divide the object much as did Democritus with his atoms. Reason has to start with something; it cannot admit first cause. Try it on yourself; you will always find yourself asking what was the cause of the first cause.

Genesis tells us that first cause is fiat: Let there be light! What is "fiat"? It is action (decision). So when Planck discovers that light is a quantum of action, he is discovering "fiat," the same fiat described in Genesis, the light that was created on the first day. But, you say, God is the cause behind the first cause. (3) The question of whether God (action) is different from light (action) is a mystery that I cannot resolve. I suspect misplaced concreteness.

I'm not implying that revealed religion is necessarily correct. As St. Gregory, a contemporary of St. Basil and an equally pious philosopher, said (as paraphrased by Sheldon Williams):

The Language of Scripture does not reveal the truth directly but a half concealed version of it. This is because the sensible world from which it draws its illustration is an imperfect copy of the intelligible. (4)

 

One would think St. Gregory had been reading Eddington, who says:

 

The physicist draws up an elaborate plan of the atom and then proceeds critically to erase each detail in turn. What is left is the atom of modern physics. (5)

In other words, we can trust neither reason nor revealed religion alone; we need both. This does not mean that all reasoned interpretations of scripture are correct, quite the contrary. But when we can find so close an equivalence as exists between the prerational accounts of light as the beginning of things on the one hand and modem physics on the other, then I think it is at last possible to begin to correctly interpret the symbolic statements of revealed religion.

Here we must be careful not to go astray, as has so often been done, and it is to guard against this possibility that I invoke quantum physics. Not all physics, which is often as much a slave to rationalism as is philosophy. Recall the physicist who insisted that the atom "could not be divided because the word atom means indivisible." Or recall the vicissitudes of the theory of light, which went from corpuscles, to waves in an ether, to quanta of action. Such a history implies that something was forcing the concept of light to grow in a way that rationalism could not have provided. This factor is, of course, experimental evidence, but it had to manifest through particular facts, such as the discrepancy in how radiation varies with temperature, which forced Planck to invent a new theory.

Perhaps the reader will think, "Well, physics is already the revealed religion of the present time-you are just creating a new sect." But it is quite to the contrary: I'm attempting to show that the hard-won truths of physics, those that have forced the most radical departures, are equivalent to what the best earlier thinkers discovered in revealed religion.

Thus, rather than creating another sect, I'm asking for an examination in depth, which I affirm can effect not only a confirmation of what was formerly faith, but a synthesis of science, which today is becoming so severely fragmented that it is losing all meaning and would stand to benefit as much as would religion.

So much, then, for the overall picture. We have dealt in the last two chapters with the many-faceted problem of light, all aspects of which point one way: to the ultimate centrality or primacy of light as the origin of everything. And by everything I mean not only matter, which light creates by its condensation from photons and which it changes by the interaction of photons with atoms and molecules, but also what St. Basil called the intelligible world, the eternal now of consciousness.

Perhaps it will be discovered that tachyons, those supposed entities which travel faster than light, may comprise the intelligible world. As to that, I will not attempt to say. I will be content if I can carry the reader to the border of this kingdom in which, paradoxically, he already resides.    

 

Preview of later chapters

In the chapters that follow we will trace evolution through the kingdoms of nature. We will find that as the entities of nature develop into higher and higher orders of organization-from particles to atoms, from atoms to molecules, thence to cells, organisms, and animals-they are invariably associated with an intrinsic activity. This intrinsic activity is the positive factor behind evolution and for two important reasons cannot be dismissed. One is theoretical, that a universe of inert particles (billiard balls) could not in itself construct the highly ordered and extremely complex entities which we call living creatures; and the other is that quantum physics has discovered in the quantum of action just such an innate activity.  

The quantum of action, as it occurs, for example, in visible light, involves an extremely small amount of energy as compared with the energy we exert to walk about or drive an automobile, but this comparison is misleading. Just as the energy required to steer an automobile is minute compared with the energy required to propel it, so too the energy required in deciding to move our own body is minute compared with the energy of actually moving. Our body is, in fact, an elaborate mechanism in which muscles are controlled by nerves, and nerves by minute electrical changes such as are involved in changing the bond in a molecule. Changing the bond in a molecule is just what the quantum of action can effect, but the difference between the creation of a starch molecule from carbon dioxide and water (which is accomplished in chlorophyll by a quantum of light) and human decision is so great that we need to trace with care how nature has evolved from the chlorophyll molecule to creatures, of the complexity of animals and man.  

In this evolution the quantum of action will be found to have a central role. While it is itself invisible and unknowable (one of its other names is the quantum of uncertainty), it persists through the whole chain of being and "causes" the progressive movement of evolution, much as by current theory of evolution, accident is said to cause mutation and hence evolution. Since the quantum of uncertainty manifests in particles and atoms in random fashion, it may be thought of as accident, but this designation becomes inappropriate in later stages when higher organisms develop and invest the intrinsic randomness with a highly competent organization; for in this case, the intrinsic randomness seems more like "play" than accident, much as, in childhood, play results in mere accident, but in later life play can refer to the activity of a skilled athlete or a gifted virtuoso.

There is in all creation this transcendence of what is strictly rational or implied by its antecedents, and the word "play" comes a little closer than the word "accident" to describing the cause of new creations, whether they be those of the mathematician, the poet, the painter, or even the progress of evolution itself. The point is, we must free ourselves from the compulsion to view everything as having an antecedent or cause, or, in the name of science, to invert means and ends. It would not occur to us to say the creativity of Beethoven was due to his learning to play the piano; in fact, we would recognize that learning the mechanics of music was part of the means that Beethoven employed to transmit his creations. In a like manner, we should put first things first in interpreting nature, and think of the organisms as the means which the divine play uses to express its exuberance, rather than to presume that all of life can be explained as caused by laws.  

Laws describe constraints; they do not create. We must posit a universe which does both, and in what follows we will endeavor to trace the interplay of these two primary forces - the creative play and the laws of necessity.

Since most science deals only in the latter, leaving evolution to be explained as accident, we can say that we are setting up a new paradigm or model for the universe, a paradigm which deals expressly with the interplay of freedom and constraint. But we cannot do this without careful attention to what science has found. This testimony is all the more valuable because, contrary to the former belief of science in the omnipotence of law, quantum physics has discovered that uncertainty or play is the most fundamental entity of all and is more basic than the fundamental particles it can create.  

So we will follow the quantum of uncertainty as it falls into matter. Chapters IV and V establish the broad outlines of the fall and subsequent ascent.  

Chapters VI to IX fill in the details as confirmed in the evolution of atoms (VI), molecules (VII), plants (VIII), and animals (IX). Chapter X ventures into territory implied by the theory but not recognized by science, and Chapter XI examines animal instinct in the light of the principles implied in Chapter X.

Chapters XII to XV carry our thesis to its conclusion: the evolution of man and beyond.

1. Hexameron V2, 5:40c-41a, 7:45a. Quoted in Williams, I. P. Sheldon. The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy. Edited by A. H. Armstrong. London: Cambridge University Press, 1967.

2. Whitmont, Edward C. The Symbolic Quest. New York: G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1969.

3. We could also say that there is no reason for light not to have an antecedent. For light to be first cause means only that its antecedents do not imply the result. See discussion of the turn at the opening of Chapter V.

4. Ibid.

5. Eddington, Arthur S. New Pathways in Science (p. 259). London: Cambridge University Press, 1947; Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1959.

 

The Reflexive Universe

   

      Mindfire