*

CANTOR'S INFINITIES

Arthur M. Young

In the late nineteenth century, Georg Cantor devised what was considered a formal system for dealing with infinity. His system defined the infinity of natural numbers, and contrasted it with the infinity of the continuum. To do this he first developed a method whereby the rational numbers (fractions) could be counted, i.e., put in one-to-one correspondence with the integers:

He then placed the rational numbers on a line representing the continuum:

Cantor next said that there must be many more points, points that correspond to the numbers  and so on, which, being irrational, were not included in the fractions already inserted. The number of such irrationals (and transcendentals), he concluded, represented a higher order of infinity.

The Cantor proof has never been convincing to me. Firstly, I am bothered by the assumption that, because it is possible to set up a procedure for putting the fractions in one-to-one correspondence with the whole numbers, therefore the number of fractions is the same as the number of whole numbers. Again, we have an obligation to distinguish between numbers that have clear and distinct values (the fractions) and irrational numbers, which can only be approximated and which, as we will show, do not occur in nature. There is also the question of whether infinity is properly a number at all. Is it not by definition that which lacks the very property numbers denote?

In any case the Cantor "proof" brushes my feelings aside like uninvited guests. Since it is these very feelings that I depend upon to appreciate a mathematical proof ­ and that in fact are the source of mathematical intuition ­ I cannot in their absence retain my interest in the subject. This does not dispose me in favor of the proof.

I am left with a similar feeling when I hear of certain modern economists who proclaim that it makes no difference how much the nation goes into debt. But this kind of objection does not refute the formalism and cannot be used as a valid objection to Cantor's method.

Seeing the assent of authorities to Cantor's proof, I begin to feel a division that cuts me off from the pursuit of mathematics, which makes me feel that there is something misguided about the subject. This sense of uneasiness often occurs when I study a new subject, and experience has taught me that this negative reaction to a new teaching generally passes in a few months.

This happened when I first encountered some of the facts of aerodynamics, such as the Magnus effect by which a rotating drum causes the incident wind to divide and the greater part of it to go around one side. It goes against common sense that the pressure of air is less on the side where the greatest amount of air is passing. Ultimately I was able to satisfy myself that this did make sense, thanks to the realization that the air at rest presses equally in all directions. When air is forced to move in one direction the average motion of particles in that direction increases, which implies that the average motion in the sideways direction (at right angles to the wind) is slower (the air particles have a slower motion), creating less pressure or a partial vacuum. This, the so-called Bernoulli effect, is the reason there is a vacuum on the upper surface of an air­plane wing and is the main cause of its lift.

But for the fifty-odd years since I first encountered Cantor's proof, I have discovered no such salutary escape from my first uneasiness.

The latter part of Cantor's argument, on the other hand, can be more easily refuted. Having put all the rational numbers in order on a line, so goes the argument, we find that  is not represented. We are thus required to conclude that there are gaps between the densely packed rational numbers, this despite the fact that there are an infinity of rational numbers between any two that can be named. Then, the argument continues, since there are an infinity of gaps, and each gap can be shown to contain as many points as the original gap (see Figure 12), there must be a larger infinity of points on the line than have been marked by the rational numbers.

One could object that since the gaps are infinitely small, it is by no means clear that they contain an infinity of points. But a more pertinent objection is that, accepting that each gap contains an infinity of points, if we stand back and ask ourselves what's going on, we realize that by putting points in the continuum we are not filling in the continuum, we are dividing it. We began with one gap to fill; we now have an infinity of gaps. We must be going in the wrong direction! A point is discrete. It is a discontinuity. We are reminded that the continuum is the absence of any point, not a plurality of points. It is as though we were trying to define an express train by saying that it makes an infinity of stops, when an express train is defined as one that makes no stops. So the number of the continuum, if number it is to have, would be zero. There are no points on a line.

 

Paradise Lost?

It is not irrelevant that geometry elects to introduce point and line as separate undefined terms. Why then should mathematics attempt to define one in terms of the other, especially as points and lines are not the business of mathematics? I can only assume that mathematics has gone astray, or rather that those who attempt to logicize mathematics have become seduced by formalism. In describing Cantor's proof, even Courant and Robbins, whose book What Is Mathematics? (1941) is the best and clearest account of the subject I have found, and who constantly remind the reader of the importance of intuition and of practical application, are caught up in the current of the early-twentieth-century fashion for formalism. More recently, Kline's Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty (1980) shows that these much-touted certainties are in deep trouble today. The chapter that especially deals with this fall from grace is titled "Paradise Barred."

In Men of Mathematics (1937), Eric Temple Bell also devotes a chapter, which he called "Paradise Lost," to Cantor and his proofs. Although I've read this chapter many times I can't make out to which paradise Bell refers, but he gives a good description of the controversy, giving a blow-by-blow account of objections to Cantor by Kronecker ("God made the integers, the rest were made by man"), Hilbert and Brouwer. He includes a quotation from Bertrand Russell that indicates the enthusiasm Cantor inspired:

Zeno was concerned with three problems. . . the infinitesimal, the infinite, and continuity. From his day to our own the finest intellects of each generation in turn attacked these problems, but achieved, broadly speaking, nothing.

Weierstrass, Dedekind and Cantor have completely solved them. Their solutions. . . are so clear as to leave no longer the slightest doubt of difficulty. This achievement is probably the greatest of which the age can boast. . . The problem of the infinitesimal was solved by Weierstrass, the solution to the other two was begun by Dedekind and definitely accomplished by Cantor. (quoted from R. E. Mortiz, Memorabilia Mathematica, 1914)

Bell goes on to say:

The enthusiasm of this passage warms us even today, although we know that Russell in the second edition (1924) of his and A. N. Whitehead's Principia Mathematica admitted that all was not well with the Dedekind "Cut" which is the spinal cord of analysis. Nor is it well today. . . Not one of the finalities of Russell's remarks of 1901 survived. . . Today for every competent expert on the side of the prophets there is an equally competent expert against them. (p. 557)

Rather than attempt to do justice to the history and changing status of Cantor's work, let me again introduce what I think to be the source of the controversy - the failure to realize that a formalism cannot in principle give a final or complete account. The formalism is a tool much as a computer is a tool; it does not answer fundamental questions, nor can it be expected to. This is because it must be objective, just as language must be objective, and this precludes it from speaking to the more fundamental issues, which are projective. To illustrate the difference, let us examine just one of the items involved in Cantor's proof, the one that says the number of points in a part of a line are same as the number in the whole line:

The line is AB, the part of the line is AB1. Take point 0 not on line AB. Draw line OB, then swing AB1 to intersect OB at D. From any point C on line AB we can project the ray DC, which intersects AD at C1. For any point C there is a corresponding point C1.

But note that it makes no difference how far the line AD is from 0. We could just as well take the much shorter line ab and show that there is a point c on ab that corresponds to C. In fact we could carry the line ab back to 0 where it Would vanish in the periphery of the point. But the point is dimensionless, so its periphery is zero.

In other words an infinity of possible directions can be extended from o. (Which recalls the much-maligned medieval speculation: How many angels [angles] can dance on the head of a pin? - Infinitely many.) In any case as many directions extend from the point as there are points in the line. More, in fact, since for every line OC there is a line in the opposite direction which does not meet C.

Note that we are not saying there are an infinity of points on the line; we are only saying that we can designate as many points by this method as we have means to distinguish them.

It is interesting to imagine the practical problem posed by filling the line with points. Suppose we were to take a line 1 cm long, which is 100,000,000 angstroms. (An angstrom is approximately the diameter of an atom.) Suppose this line were drawn on the face of a crystal. We could designate a point at each of the nuclei of 100 million atoms distributed along the length, but then we would find between each nucleus a gap 100,000 times the diameter of each nucleus. Aside from the sheer number of points (now 10 (to the 5th) X 10 (to the 8th) = 10 (to the 13th), (ten trillion), we would not be able to deal with these small dimensions because the energy would go up as we tried to measure smaller dimensions. We would be prevented from carrying out Cantor's program.

Of course, you say, Cantor's proof does not purport to be practical, it is theoretical. This is, however, the main point of the uncertainty principle. The increased precision cannot in principle be obtained. The world is bounded by a wall that prevents access to zero just as effectively as it prevents access to infinity. This limitation is set by physics, but it depends on first principles; it is not a mere practical limit, so we are not permitted to ignore it.

The same applies to Zeno's argument that the arrow at each instant is at rest and therefore cannot move. The arrow at each instant is not at rest, because the instant must always have duration, and in this duration it is moving. So we must ask ourselves how we so easily made the assumption that the arrow is at rest at each instant when, to put it bluntly, there is no such thing as an instant.

Is this "instantaneous view" not a pure presumption manufactured by mind? A very useful one to be sure, but not to be trusted in an inquiry into first principles. This view of Zeno's paradox thus disposes of the idea of higher infinities in much the same way that relativity disposes of the idea of simultaneity.

 

Rationals and Irrationals

The Cantor proof of higher infinities depends upon the notion that there is an uncountable number of irrational numbers that can be located in the continuum as points on a line. In "The Queen and Mr. Russell," I made the point that there is a fundamental distinction between putting rational fractions on a line and putting the irrational numbers on a line, in that the geometrical construction that produces an irrational on the plane (e.g., as the diagonal of the unit square) has to be transferred to the line. As I said in that essay, the square root of two is an inhabitant of the plane, not of the line.

I now suspect that this doesn't get to the heart of the problem, which involves the distinction between a linear dimension and the two simultaneous dimensions of a plane. The fact that we can draw a line on the plane is misleading, because the line on a plane permits comparison and measurement. If we were confined to one dimension we could not measure, because the ruler and that which it measures could not be separated. (See "A Formalism for Philosophy" and "Constraint and Freedom" in Which Way Out [1980].)

Perhaps the simplest example of dividing the line involves the string of a musical instrument, which would normally vibrate at the lowest frequency, the "fundamental."

When the string is restrained at its center, it will vibrate at twice the fundamental; when restrained one-third of the way, at three times the fundamental, and so on. This provides a way of creating fractional time intervals. It does not depend on the exact distance; it is in the nature of the string to vibrate at these integral values of frequency. The same thing occurs in quantum phenomena - the frequencies of atoms are in an integral relation to one another (eigenstates).

Another example of rational or exact fractional division of time can be produced with gear wheels. Two shafts can be caused to rotate at speeds with an exact ratio by making gear wheels the number of whose teeth are in the required ratio. This does not depend on the accuracy of the gear teeth, just on their number. An irrational ratio cannot be so produced.

This implies that there is a sense in which the irrational numbers are abstractions that are only encountered through measurement or calculation - they are "components" of the natural numbers. They do not themselves occur in nature. Thus, instead of considering the diagonal of the unit square as  we could consider that the sides of a square whose diagonal is 2 are .

This is well illustrated by the device of describing the circle as the locus of points from which two rays at right angles meet the ends of a line that is the diameter of the circle:

We can think of the line AB as the unit and the lines AC and CB as "components." We only encounter irrational numbers in nature when we compute the value of such components.

 

The Ideal and the Real

By engaging our minds in proofs and demonstrations that are often quite elegant, mathematics leads us to believe that it deals in an ideal world, one removed from the jumbled confusion of phenomena, a world that is unchanging and perfect. This view of mathematics as "the world of pure form," of "certainty of results," exemplified in the proofs of geometry and in almost all purely mathematical operations, seems to contrast sharply with the approximate nature of human and natural constructions - the variety and deviation from the ideal that characterizes the world of physical objects.

But the findings of science in the last hundred years point toward an opposite conclusion. The works of nature are, in fact, extremely precise, perhaps perfectly precise.

Nowhere is this precision more in evidence than in the atomic kingdom. The simplest demonstration is the fact that all atoms have been found to be organizations of an integral number of proton/electron pairs, which give what is known as the atomic number.

A further example of the extreme precision of the atomic world is illustrated in the Mossbauer effect, by which it is possible to measure a motion of a few centimeters a second by the variation in absorption of radiation by the nucleus of the atom. This process implies an accuracy of frequency response better than one part in ten billion, far beyond our ability to measure. The nucleus of the atom exercises this discrimination despite the fact that the wavelength of the incident radiation is about six thousand times greater than the diameter of the nucleus.

Again we have atomic clocks, which have replaced the rotation of the earth as a criterion for measuring time. The atomic clock can measure a variation in the earth's rotation of less than one second per century. This exact precision is far beyond our ability to measure in any other way and hence establishes a standard that may well be absolute.

But such precision is not confined exclusively to the atomic world. The immune system of the human body has the capacity to detect the presence of an organ transplanted from anyone of some four billion other inhabitants of the globe, a discriminatory power on a par with that of atoms.

What all this suggests is that "the world of pure form" is not confined to the celestial sphere. Nor is it to be found only in pure mathematics. The material world, in its own way, is incredibly, perhaps infinitely, precise.

 

The Dedekind Cut

This question of "real" perfection can help clear up the difficulty surrounding one of the well known "proofs" of mathematics, the so-called Dedekind cut. The Dedekind cut involves the same problem as Cantor's proof of higher infinities, since it proposes a system for locating irrational numbers in the continuum. It has, however, long been questioned for its own implicit treatment of infinity.

Dedekind was troubled by the problem of putting  on the line between one and two. His method was to assume a rule that divides all natural numbers into two classes, in this case the class of rational numbers less than  and the class of rational numbers greater than  . is thus the "cut" or gap between these classes. (It is assumed by some mathematicians that the Dedekind cut can be achieved without reference to geometry, but doing so would still involve a quadratic equation, and hence two orthogonal dimensions.)

Dedekind's method depends, as did Cantor's system, on infinitely small distances or measures. And since, as we have seen, the infinitely small, whether in distance or time, is only obtainable with infinite energy, it is impossible to achieve.

The standard objection to such an argument is that in mathematics we are not concerned with practicality; we are dealing in theory. (Eddington once said he would never have proposed 10 (to the 79th) as the number of protons in the universe if he thought anyone was going to count them.) But here we have the case of practice and theory merging in the Heisenberg uncertainty principle.

The uncertainty principle is a consequence of Planck's discovery that action comes in whole units that cannot be less than a certain size, a sort of indivisible "atom" of action. So deeply does it penetrate into the foundations of physics that the distinction between theory and practice breaks down. A similar import could be claimed for the speed of light and a small number of other constants of nature. These constants are at once empirical and theoretical, empirical because their values are found by experiment, and theoretical because, once found, they become the basis for theoretical deductions.

The question then becomes, does the theoretical limit to smallness that physics has been obliged to accept (to its ultimate benefit) penetrate into mathematical theory? The ready answer, again, would be no. But insofar as mathematics deals with first causes it can no longer indulge this separation of fact from theory. We can formulate this as a principle: An operation that cannot in practice be performed should require that the theory be revised to anticipate the practical limitation.

We will come back to this issue later.

 

The Transcendentals

Is it possible that Cantor had a valid insight but, as is often the case, distorted it by misinterpretation? Essentially what he says is that there is something beyond infinity.

Perhaps by introducing some ideas I've had for a long time together with the conclusions we've reached here we can arrive at a speculation that would account for Cantor's inspiration and justify some of the acceptance he has been accorded. However, these ideas, while reasonable and straightforward, are even more foreign to what is accepted in mathematics than were Cantor's - in fact, we could say that Cantor's error was to accommodate to the usual thinking.

The ideas to be put together are:

1. Numbers can better be defined as successive divisions of unity rather than as additions to unity as Peano's axioms assume. (This is a point developed in "The Queen and Mr. Russell." I have recently noticed that Eddington says the same thing in The Philosophy of Physical Science: "Wave mechanics thus brings the integers [which form the whole material of our ordinary arithmetic] into its purview as the eigenvalues of one of its symbolic operators. Introduced in this way the integers are concepts unassociated with the procedure of counting." [p. 173])

2. There is but one transcendental number, or two if you count e as independent of . (e is related to by the formula:  =-1. I should acknowledge the fact that there are large classes of numbers that have been proved to be transcendental in the sense that they cannot be expressed as roots of equations, such as  + . Others, such as where b is irrational, are neither constructable nor do they possess the same empirical status as or e.

It can be argued that neither of the above classes of number "exists" apart from their definition. A theoretical number such as a transcendental, I would argue, must have some foundation in nature. In fact, if the prescription for a number were sufficient to affirm its existence, one should include unicorns, griffons, manticores, and other fabulous animals in zoological classification, of which animals found in nature would be a subset.)

3. The line or continuum does not consist of an infinity of points, nor of more points than can be put in correspondence with the infinity of natural numbers; rather the point itself makes possible the projection of an infinity of directions.

Proceeding from these assumptions, we will find that the construction that would establish directions depends on our ability to divide the 360° circle - of which is the signature - implied by the point. (The point is a circle of arbitrarily small radius.) Such construction would limit us to rational divisions of the circle.

The circle represents wholeness. In the process of dividing we would discover that each number (or perhaps each prime number) provided a unique division not obtainable by other divisions. For example ­

- an infinite series of smaller and smaller terms.

Note that if we replace one of the 1/4's, for however small a term (i.e., however high a power of the denominator), by 1/3, the infinite series collapses into an identity. Thus:

To define in terms of an infinite series we use Euler's formula:

In other words, is unique. Unlike the integers, which are expressible in terms of one other number, expression requires all the numbers (or all the odd numbers).

Other examples share this propersity:

can also be expressed as an infinite nesting of square roots.

Passing beyond technical considerations, such as whether these are the best or most general expressions of the principle, to an interpretation of the principle, we could say incorporates (or implies) all the natural numbers. And since each number can be expressed as an infinite series of inverse powers of the next higher number, can be represented as an infinite series of infinite series.

However, is not quantitatively infinite. In Euler's expression (given above) addition and subtraction alternate, and the sum approaches a certain value between 2/3 and unity. So is quantitatively finite, but includes an infinity of qualifications (natural numbers), each of which is itself "infinite" in the sense that an infinite series is required to express one number in terms of another.

We thus associate with an infinity of infinities, and since is transcendental, we could say that Cantor correctly perceived that transcendental numbers are" beyond infinity." But two misinterpretations confused Cantor's fundamental insight: 1) that infinity is a very large quantity; and 2) that what is beyond infinity is a still larger quantity - i.e., that there are an uncountably infinite number of transcendental numbers.

To put this in perspective, it could be said we have inverted Cantor and even Peano. Peano defined number as successive additions to one. This fails to bring out that a number is not just a collection of n units, it is a unity of n parts; that is, any number, say five, is both a collection of five units and a unit of five parts. Once this is recognized, the definition of number as successive divisions can be appreciated.

The inversion of Cantor is justified because there does not, in fact, appear to be an infinity of transcendental numbers. Among numbers having any application to the real world, and e alone have been proved to be transcendental. These two numbers are intimately related, and it is possible that they are not "different" numbers but aspects of the same "non-number." Since we define numbers as divisions of the whole, and is not a division but the whole itself, it is not a number.

Thus, while preserving Cantor's distinction between transcendental and other numbers, we view as the transcendental number. It is preeminent not because it is one of a higher infinity, but because it is unique.

We may in fact think of as a super number, the source of all of the other numbers. We can say this because represents the circle, a symbol for wholeness. The integers can be defined as the angular division of the circle. This also provides a definition for fractions, since given the concept of division - that the whole can be divided into n parts - each one of these is 1/nth of the whole. The real numbers can be accommodated or defined as trigonometric functions, i.e.,  is twice the sine of 45°, and so on. (This might comfort the ghost of Pythagoras.) I do not know whether all algebraic numbers could be expressed as trigonometric functions, but a plane surface does accommodate solutions to equations.

Whether or not this approach to number is more correct than the one now in use, it is safe to say that the current interpretation of natural numbers as a mere subset of larger classes of numbers is not a useful one. If the question is one of elegance or aesthetics, which are valid criteria in mathematics especially, then I regard the descent of all numbers from the unity of   as the more elegant description.

Philosophically, too, it is better to think of the universe as unity with infinite diversity than as an infinite collection, countable or uncountable. This notion, as we've pointed out, allows for quality as well as quantity. I suspect this issue is involved in Bohr's complementarity principle, which is generally interpreted to mean that for one measure to be made precisely, another measure must be imprecise. We would extend this to read that any measurement must be complemented by a quality that is different from measure. Measurement of size, for example, is incomplete without a reference to an actual object to provide scale.

In other words, quantitative measurement is in principle incomplete. Applied to mathematics, this implies that if mathematics is the science of quantity, it cannot deal with first principles; or alternatively, if mathematics is to deal with first principles - if it is to be queen of the sciences - it must recognize that which is not quantitative, which we here call quality.

The transcendental number is one way in which the limitation of quantity shows up. is neither large nor small, but it cannot be expressed in finite terms.

Cantor's mistake was to find preeminence in the quantity of transcendental numbers, whereas it is the quality of the transcendental itself that makes it unique, that makes it the "origin" capable of any direction. There is a oneness beyond everything that cannot be described because it is beyond everything. This oneness includes all that can be described.

 

Mathematics, Physics & Reality

 

Mindfire